Σάββατο 7 Δεκεμβρίου 2024

J,K. Bluntschli "The Theory of the State" (1895) General characteristics of the State Πολιτική Σκακιέρα ΚΟΙΝΩΝΙΚΗ ΣΚΕΨΗ

 


J.K.  BluntschliThe Theory of the State

The Conception and Idea of the State

General characteristics of the State

Πολιτική Σκακιέρα

ΚΟΙΝΩΝΙΚΗ ΣΚΕΨΗ

 

 

 

 

 

 

BOOK I.

 

THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE.

 

CHAPTER I.

The Conception and Idea of the State.

The general Conception of the State

 

The Conception of the State arrived at by history: the idea by philosophy.

 Characteristics of all States :

(1) a number of men ;

(2) a fixed territory ;

(3) unity ;

(4) distinction between rulers and subjects ;

(5) an organic nature.

— In what sense the State is an organism :

(a) It has spirit and body.

(b) It has members with various special functions.

(c) It develops and grows: yet is no mere natural growth.

 (6) The State is a moral and spiritual organism: it has a personality.

 (7) It is masculine,

— Note on the different names for State.

 

 

 

   THE conception (Begriff) of the State has to do with the nature and essential characteristics of actual States. The idea or ideal (Idee) of the State presents a picture, in the splendour of imaginary perfection, of the State as not yet realised, but to be striven for.

    The conception of the State can only be discovered by history; the idea of the State is called up by philosophical speculation. The universal conception of the State is recognised when the many actual States which have appeared in the world's history have been surveyed, and their common characteristics discovered. The highest idea of the State is beheld when the tendency of human nature to political society is considered, and the highest conceivable and possible development of this tendency is regarded as the political end of mankind.

 

characteristics of all States

   If we consider the great number of States which history presents to us, we become aware at once of certain common characteristics of all states; others are only seen on closer examination.

 

/ - 1. a number of men

   First, it is clear that in every State a number of men are combined. In particular States the number may be very different, some embracing only a few thousands, others many millions; but, nevertheless, we cannot talk of a State until we get beyond the circle of a single family, and until a multitude of men (i.e. families, men, women, and children) are united together. A family, a clan, can become the nucleus round which, in time, a greater number gathers, but a real State cannot be formed until that has happened, until the single family has broken up into a series of families, and kindred has become extended to the race. The horde is not yet a tribe (Volkerschaff). Without a tribe, or, at a higher stage of civilisation, without a nation (Volk)  there is no State.

  There is no normal number for the size of the population of a State; [[For Aristotle's views on this subject, cp. Pol. vii. 4: in Eth. Nic. ix. 10. § 3, he says there cannot be a State (πόλις) of ten men nor of 100,000. Cp. also Pol. iii. 3. § 5]  Rousseau's number of 10,000 men would certainly not be sufficient. In the middle ages such small States could exist with security and dignity; modern times lead to the formation of much greater States, partly because the political duties of the modern State need a greater national force, partly because the increased power of the great States readily becomes a danger and a menace to the independence of the small.

 

/ - 2. a fixed territory

   Secondly, a permanent relation of the people to the soil is necessary for the continuance of the State. The State requires its territory: nation and country go together.

   Nomadic peoples, although they have chiefs to command them and law to govern them, have not yet reached the full condition of States until they have a fixed abode. The Hebrew people received a political training from Moses, but were not a State until Joshua settled them in Palestine. In the great migrations at the fall of the Roman empire, when peoples left their old habitations and undertook to conquer new ones, they were in an uncertain state of transition. The earlier States which they had formed no longer existed: the new did not yet exist. The personal bond continued for a while — the territorial connection was broken.

   Only if they succeeded in regaining a sure footing were they enabled to establish a new State. The peoples who failed perished. The Athenians under Themistocles saved the State of Athens on their ships, because after the victory they again took possession of their city; but the Cimbri and Teutones perished, because they left their old home and failed to conquer a new one. Even the Roman State would have perished, if the Romans, after the burning of their city, had migrated to Veii.

 

/ - 3. unity.

   Another characteristic of the State is the unity of the whole, the cohesion of the nation. Internally there may indeed be different divisions with considerable independence of their own. Thus in Rome there was the patrician populus, and alongside of it the plebs. In the older Teutonic states of the middle ages there was the constitution of the people alongside of the feudal constitution. The State may also be composed of several parts which in their turn constitute States: thus from the old German Empire several territorial States have gradually grown up: in the modern federations of North America and Switzerland, and in the new German Empire, a common collective State (Gesammtstat) and a number of confederated local States exist together. But unless the community forms a coherent whole in its internal organisation, or can appear and act as a unit in external relations, there is no State.

 

/ - 4. Disctinction between rulers and subjects

  In all States we find the distinction (Gcgensatz) between governors and governed, or — to adopt an old expression rulers and which has been sometimes misunderstood, sometimes misused, but which in itself is neither hateful nor slavish — between sovereign and subjects. This distinction appears in the most manifold forms, but is always necessary. Even in the most extreme democracy in which it may seem to vanish, it is nevertheless present. The assembly of the Athenian citizens was the sovereign, the individual Athenians were its subjects.

   Where there is no longer any sovereign possessing authority, where the governed have renounced political obedience, and every one does that which is right in his own eyes, this is anarchy and the State is at an end. Anarchy, like all negations, cannot last, so that out of it there at once arises, perhaps in a rude and often cruel form of despotism, some sort of new sovereignty which compels obedience, and thus reproduces that indispensable distinction.

[ Communists deny this in theory, but in doing so, they deny the State itself. Even they have nowhere been able by annihilating the State to introduce a merely social union, and, if they ever succeed in temporarily winning over the masses to their projects, we may be certain, from the example of the religious communists of the sixteenth century, the Anabaptists, and from the natural consequences of events, that they too would again set up a domination, and that the harshest that has ever been. ]

  Among the Slavonic peoples we find the old idea that only the unanimity of all the members of a community represents the common will, and that neither the majority nor any higher authority can decide. This principle however can at the most only serve as a principle of local communities, and that only among a people where all easily and quickly agree; it can never be a political principle, for the State must override the unavoidable opposition of individuals.

 

/ - 5. an organic nature.

  The State is in no way a lifeless instrument, a dead machine: it is a living and therefore organised being. This organic nature of the State has not always been understood. Political peoples had indeed an image (Vorstellung) of it, and recognized it consciously in language, but the insight into the political organism remained long concealed from political science, and even at the present day many publicists (Statsgelehrte) fail to understand it. It is the especial merit of the German school of historical jurists to have recognized the organic nature of the Nation and the State. This conception refutes both the mathematical and mechanical view of the State, and the atomistic way of treating it, which forgets the whole in the individuals. An oil-painting is something other than a mere aggregation of drops of oil and colour, a statue is something other than a combination of marble particles, a man is not a mere quantity of cells and blood corpuscles; and so too the nation is not a mere sum of citizens, and the State is not a mere collection of external regulations.

   The State indeed is not a product of nature, and therefore it is not a natural organism; it is indirectly the work of man. The tendency to political life is to be found in human nature, and so far the State has a natural basis; but the realisation of this political tendency has been left to human labour [[Cp. Arist. Pol. i. 2. § 15, 12533. a. 30: “ φύσει μὲν οὖν ὁρμὴ ἐν πᾶσιν ἐπὶ τὴν τοιαύτην κοινωνίαν· δὲ πρῶτος συστήσας μεγίστων ἀγαθῶν αἴτιος.”], and human arrangement, and so far the State is a product of human activity, and its organism is a copy of a natural organism.

In what sense a State is an organism

   In calling the State an organism we are not thinking of in what the activities by which plants and animals seek, consume state is an and assimilate nourishment, and reproduce their species. We are thinking rather of the following characteristics of natural organisms : —

(a) Every organism is a union of soul and body, i. e. of material elements and vital forces.

(b) Although an organism is and remains a whole, yet in its parts it has members, which are animated by special motives and capacities, in order to satisfy in various ways the varying needs of the whole itself.

(c) The organism develops itself from within outwards, and has an external growth.

 

   In all three respects the organic nature of the State is evident.

   - (a). The State has spirit and body.

    In the State spirit and body, will and active organs are necessarily bound together in one life. The one national spirit and spirit, which is something different from the average sum of the contemporary spirit of all citizens, is the spirit of the State; the one national will, which is different from the average will of the multitude, is the will of the State.

   The constitution, with its organs for representing the whole and expressing the will of the State in laws, with a head who governs, with all sorts of offices and magistracies for administration, with courts to exercise public justice, with institutions of all kinds to provide for the intellectual and material interests of the community, with an army to express the public force — this constitution is the body of the State, it is the form in which the nation manifests its common life. Individual States differ like individual men in spirit, character, and form. The progress of mankind depends essentially on the emulation of its component peoples and states.

 

   - (b). The State has members with various special functions.

   The constitution is likewise the articulation of the body politic. Every office and every political assembly is a particular member with its own proper functions. An office is not like part of a machine, it has not to exert merely mechanical activities which always remain the same, like the wheels and spindles in a factory, which always do the same thing in the same way. Its functions have a spiritual character, and vary on particular occasions according to the needs of public life, which they have to satisfy: they serve life, and are themselves living. Where an office becomes lifeless, sinks into unthinking formalism, and becomes like a machine, there the office itself is ruined, and the State, by becoming a machine, inevitably falls.

   (The spirit of office)

   Not only the official, but the office itself has a psychical significance, it is animated by a soul. An office has a character and a spirit which in its turn influences the person who acts in it. Even a very ordinary man when elected to the Roman consulship had his character elevated and his natural vigour increased by the dignity, majesty, and power of his office. The office of judge is so sacred, so consecrated to justice, that even a weakling when appointed to it has his mind ennobled and his determination aroused to maintain the right. The spirit of the office cannot indeed alter the nature of the official, it is not powerful enough so to permeate the character that the individual always fully represents the significance of his office; yet every official experiences some psychical influence on his spirit and disposition, and if he has an impressionable mind it cannot escape him that his office itself has a soul which, for the present, is in a close and immediate connection with his own individuality, but which is different from him, and more enduring.

   - (c.) The State develops and grows.

   Nations and States have a development and a growth of their own. The periods of national and political history are to be measured by great eras which far surpass the age of individual men; the latter may be measured by years and tens of years, the former extend beyond centuries. Every period again has its special character, and the collective history of a nation and state is a coherent whole. The childhood of nations has a different character from their maturity, and every statesman is compelled to consider the time of life in which his State happens to be. 'There is a time for everything.'

   (Yet is no mere natural growth)

   Along with this affinity to the development of natural organism there is an important difference. The life of plants, animals, and men grows and decays in regular periods and stages, but the development of States and political institutions is not always as regular. The influence of human free will or of external fate frequently produces considerable deviations, checking, hastening, sometimes reversing the normal movement, according as it is broken in upon by great and strong individuals, or by the wild passions of the nation itself. These deviations are indeed neither so numerous, nor are they commonly so important as to invalidate the general rule. On the contrary, they are much rarer and generally much slighter than is fancied by those whose opinions are determined by the immediate impressions of contemporary events. Yet they are weighty enough to show that the idea of a mere natural growth of the State is one-sided and unsatisfactory, and that we must allow full play even here to the free action of individuals.

 

/ - 6. The State is a moral and spiritual organism

   Whilst history explains the organic nature of the State, we learn from it at the same time that the State does not stand on the same grade with the lower organisms of plants and animals, but is of a higher kind; we learn that it is a moral and spiritual organism, a great body which is capable of taking up into itself the feelings and thoughts of the nation, of uttering them in laws, and realising them in acts; we are informed of moral qualities and of the character of each State. History ascribes to the State a personality which, having spirit and body, possesses and manifests a will of its own.

   The glory and honour of the State have always elevated the heart of its sons, and animated them to sacrifices. For freedom and independence, for the rights of the State, the noblest and best have in all times and in all nations expended their goods and their lives. To extend the reputation and the power of the State, to further its welfare and its happiness, has universally been regarded as one of the most honourable duties of gifted men. The joys and sorrows of the State have always been shared by all its citizens. The whole great idea of Fatherland and love of country would be inconceivable if the State did not possess this high moral and personal character.

   (The State has a personality)

  The recognition of the personality of the State is thus not less indispensable for Public Law (Statsrecht) than for International Law (Volkerrechf).

   A person in the juridical sense is a being to whom we can ascribe a legal will (Rechtswille) who can acquire, create and possess rights. In the realm of public law this conception is as significant as in the realm of private law. The State is par excellence a person in the sense of public law (offentlich-rechtliche Person). The purpose of the whole constitution is to enable the person of the State to express and realise its will (Statswille) which is different from the individual wills of all individuals, and different from the sum of them.

   The personality of the State is, however, only recognized by free people, and only in the civilised nation-state has it attained to full efficacy. In the earlier stages of politics only the prince is prominent; he alone is a person, and the State is merely the realm of his personal rule.

 

/ - 7. The State is masculine.

   The same is true with regard to the masculine character of the modern State. This becomes first apparent in contrast with the feminine character of the Church. A religious community may have all the other characteristics of a political community, yet she does not wish to be a State, and is not a State, just because she does not consciously rule herself like a man, and act freely in her external life, but wishes only to serve God and perform her religious duties.

   To put together the result of this historical consideration, the general conception of the State may be determined as follows: — the State is a combination or association (Gesammtheit) of men, in the form of government and governed, on a definite territory, united together into a moral organised masculine personality; or, more shortly — the State is the politically organised national person of a definite country.

 

Note:

   In my “Pyschological Studies on State and Church” (Zurich, 1845) the masculine character of the State has been more exactly worked out. The French expression, L’etat c’est l’homme, does not merely signify 'the State is Man in general' (der Mensch im Groszen), but 'the State is the man, the husband (der Mann) in general,' as the Church represents the womanly nature in general, the wife (die Frau).

[It may be as well to note that in German the word Stat is masculine and the word Kirche feminine !]

 

 

   Different names of the State

Notes. —1.

   It is not without interest to observe how different peoples have named the State.

   The Greeks still signified city and state by the same word, πόλις — a sign that their conception of the State was based on the city, and was limited by the city point of view.

   The Roman expression, civitas, refers likewise to the citizenship of a city as the nucleus of the State, but has more of a personal character than the Greek word, and is better adapted to take up into itself greater masses of people. It speaks too for the high significance of the State, that the expression 'civilisation' is derived from the name of the State, and practically coincides with the extension and realisation of the State.

   In a certain way the other Roman name, res fublica, stands still higher, in so far as it contains not merely a reference to the citizenship of a city, but to a people (res populi), and a regard to the people's welfare. In the sense of the ancients the expression Republic does not exclude Monarchy but does not apply to despotic governments. [Cp. Engl. 'Commonwealth.']

    In modern languages the expression 'State' is the prevailing one, not only in the Romance but in the Teutonic languages (stato, etat, Stat). In itself completely indifferent (it signifies originally any condition, and at first the fuller expression status reipublicae was required in order to bring out a more exact reference to the State), this term in course of time has become the most universal denomination of the State, unambiguous and needing no qualification. Although 'the established,' 'what stands,' is brought into prominence, this connexion is put aside, and the word signifies not the existing arrangement and at first the fuller expression status reipublicae was required in order to bring out a more exact reference to the State), this term in course of time has become the most universal denomination of the State, unambiguous and needing no qualification. Although 'the established,' 'what stands,' is brought into prominence, this connexion is put aside, and the word signifies not the existing arrangement and constitution of the State (Πολιτεία), but the State which can outlive even a complete transformation of the form of government.

   All other modern expressions have only limited validity; e.g. the proud word Reich only applies to great states under a monarchical organisation, and suggests likewise a combination of several relatively independent countries, like the Latin word imperium (Fr. and Engl. empire), in which at the same time there is an allusion to the imperial (kaiserlich) rule.

   More narrow is the sense of the word 'country' (Land), which primarily signifies the external territory of the State — (and of a state that is not broken up into separate parts), but secondarily is applied to the State itself which has this territory. This expression forms the natural counterpart to the Greek πόλις, since it bases the State primarily on the country (Landschaft), while the other bases it on the city.

   The fine word 'Fatherland' is still narrower, by virtue of its relation to the individual; but at the same time it is elevated and spiritualised by the reference to the personal connexion and transmission of blood relationships in the country: in this word is expressed with clearness and with feeling the whole love and devotion of the individual citizen to the great and living whole to which he belongs with his body, with whose existence his own is bound up, and for which to sacrifice himself is the highest glory of man.

 (βλ. Ευριπίδη Φοίνισσαι, στ. 369-371

«    Αλλ’ αναγκαίως έχει

Πατρίδος εράν άπαντας. ός δ’ άλλως λέγει

Λόγοισι χαίρει, τόν δέ νουν εκείσ’ έχει. »  

  βλ. Schiller’s William Tell

'Cleave to thy fatherland, thy country dear,

 And with thy whole heart cling thou closely to it.

 For rooted in thy country is thy strength;

 Away in yon strange world thou stand'st alone.'

 

 

 

 

pp. 15-24.

 

 

 

 

J.K.  BluntschliThe Theory of the State

The Conception and Idea of the State

General characteristics of the State

Πολιτική Σκακιέρα

ΚΟΙΝΩΝΙΚΗ ΣΚΕΨΗ

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 


Δεν υπάρχουν σχόλια:

Δημοσίευση σχολίου

P.V. Petrovas "εν αναμονή" φωτογραφία

  P . V . Petrovas « εν αναμονή » φωτογραφία                     ΕΛΕΥΘΕΡΟΓΡΑΦΟΣ eleftherografos . blogspot . com [ ...